One thing I
found particularly thought provoking about Imagined Communities was Anderson’s
reoccurring argument that education and universities were a principal force
behind the development of nationalism. In a sense, I found this argument
counterintuitive – after all, philosophy, mathematics, science, etc., are
generally undertaken with the aim of developing universal ideas that are not
bounded by borders or national identities. Certainly, Anderson’s argument in
Chapter 7, about the nation-building role of educational infrastructure and
bureaucratic pilgrimages, was very convincing. More challenging, however, is his
assertion in Chapter 5 that the move towards nationalism was led by linguists,
philosophers, and historians, who created national universities that promoted
vernacular languages. Anderson may still be right here, but my initial reaction
was that these types of institutions might be more likely to foster
internationalism rather than harden allegiances to the national imagined
community.
I suppose my
hesitation to accept this argument may be informed by a general attitude of
distrust that I have always had towards nationalism. But this book challenged
that conception. In his introduction, Anderson eloquently sums up the source of
this distrust, writing, “unlike some other isms, nationalism has never produced
its own grand thinkers: no Hobbeses, Toquevilles, Marxes of Webers. This ‘emptiness’ easily gives rise… to
a certain condescension” (5). Instead, Anderson argues, “it would… make things
easier if one considered [nationalism] as if it belonged with ‘kinship’ or
‘religion,’ rather than with ‘liberalism or ‘fascism.’”
I thought this
argument was particularly well illustrated by Anderson’s discussion of the revolutions in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. As
Anderson and many historians have pointed out, it is reductive to consider the
many revolutions of this period as motivated by similar ambitions and elements in society.
Rather, these revolutions ran the gamut from progressive to deeply
conservative. As Anderson describes in Chapter 4, a great number of the
revolutions in the Americas were actually oriented towards preserving the
past, often in the form of a slaveholding society. On the other hand, some revolutions
of this period were oriented towards a more utopian project of building a new
future, with the French Revolution being the most notable example. Ultimately,
this comparison of revolutions helped me understand Anderson’s point that nationalism is not a
fully developed political ideology. Rather, for a multitude of contingent
reasons, nationalism emerged towards the end of the eighteenth century as an
increasing fact of life and a popular vehicle for political activity.
No comments:
Post a Comment