Although
I had read excerpts from Benedict Anderson's “Imagined Communities”
before, I had never focused so intently on the questions he poses in
the book; his definition of nationalism as an “imagined political
community – and imagined as both inherently limited and sovereign”
serves well enough for discussions of national politics and the
ethics surrounding those issues in other courses. But of course
a course on Imagined Networks would take this piece more seriously;
and with good reason.
Nevertheless,
it is difficult to move away from concepts and conceits that we've
carried with us for years, and so it was the discussion on patriotism
and racism that interested me the most; I had, for instance, already
read the (now commonly quoted) truth that dying “for one's country,
which usually one does not choose, assumes a moral grandeur which
dying for the Labour Party, the American Medical Association, or
perhaps even Amnesty International cannot rival” (144), but it was
rewarding to consider the problem anew.
For it
is, most might agree, a problem; why should an involuntary
association with a body, even one so powerful in the imagination as
the nation, be seen as morally superior to an association with a body
that one chose? Most might say that there is nothing more moral about
being an American, say, or a Swede than there is about being an
employee of Amnesty International or the Peace Corps; but dying
for Sweden or America is constructed as so much more meaningful than
dying in a civil war in Latin America.
Which
leads nicely into the question of racism – because as proud as any
person might be of their racial and ethnic heritage (and the majority
of most people are),
racial identity is hardly any more voluntary than national identity,
being thrust upon oneself not just by the accident of birth but by
the perceptions of other people (for that perception is important,
and undergirds such occurrences as “white-passing privilege” and
the endless questions of, “What race are you? I could
have sworn you were [x]” that
any mixed-race or questionable-heritage people might face).
One of
the most interesting points that Anderson reaches at the end of his
discussion on race is the fact that “Spanish-speaking mestizo
Mexicans trace their ancestries, not to Castilian conquistadors, but
to half-obliterated Aztecs, Mayans, Toltecs and Zapotecs” (154) –
and they are not alone. Latinos up and down the Americas often
emphasize their native roots when discussing their heritage. On the
face of it, it might seem odd; both their native ancestors and their
Castilian ancestors performed the same function in terms of producing
the individual that stands here today. And yet occur it does, still,
according to Anderson because of misplaced class sentiments; a
conscious laying down of the claims to pseudo-aristocracy,
remembering the ancestors one never chose but who suffered, lived and
died under oppression to bring you here today. It is futile to deny one's ancestry; one's genetic makeup cannot be changed by fierce desire. And yet, the way that ancestry is interpreted, by others and by oneself, is so important.
No comments:
Post a Comment